Abstract
This review article provides ethical guidance for determining which kinds of financial benefits provided to living organ donors are ethically appropriate. It does so by way of ethical analysis of a policy case study: the National Kidney Registry (NKR) has implemented a donor insurance program to all its living donors. Is such a policy ethically supportable, or is it an unethical practice? The article proceeds as follows. First, a framework for grounding the ethical commitments of transplant programs is defended. It is argued that this framework can be accepted by all who work in transplant medicine, regardless of differences in ethical theory preference or background. Second, from this framework two ethical principles are formulated. (1) Living donors should, as far as possible, not be worse off for donating. (2) Disincentives towards donation should be removed as much as possible. Third, issues with unethical incentives are explored: undue inducement, commodification of the body, potential decreased organ donation rates, and potential exploitation of vulnerable populations. Lastly, these ethical considerations are applied to the policy change at the NKR, showing that the NKR policy change appears to be ethically supportable. Financial benefits provided to donors are ethically sound if they are in keeping with principles (1) and (2), and do not cause undue inducement, commodification, decreased organ donation, or exploitation. It is ethically appropriate for transplant programs to institute as well as study such programs with the goal of serving the welfare and interests of patients, donors, and the general public.
Author Contributions
Copyright© 2018
C Bester Johan, et al.
License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
Competing interests The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.
Funding Interests:
Citation:
Introduction
The provision of financial benefits to living kidney donors continue to raise ethical questions. Some financial compensations provided to donors seem reasonable, but when do such benefits cross the line and become unethical or even illegal? This article has a number of goals. First, to provide an overview of what is ethically at stake when it comes to provision of financial benefits to living donors. Second, to suggest an ethical framework that can be used to think through ethical questions when financial benefits are provided to living donors. Third, to define two ethical principles that are central to transplant programs and transplant practice, which we believe guide transplant activities relating to living donors. A hypothesis that will be defended: the framework and principles stipulated in this review will be applicable to and can be endorsed by those who engage in the care of living donors. They can be used to as an ethical guide when considering financial benefits to living donors. This review will accomplish these goals by use of a clinical case/policy example. The National Kidney Registry (NKR), the largest sharing network for kidney paired donation, considered a policy change, whereby all living donors would be offered basic life, injury, and disability insurance. Does this represent an ethical financial benefit, or should one be concerned by such a policy? How should one think through the ethical issues raised here? The goal is not to focus merely on the NKR or to address the complex issues around how post donation complications are defined. Rather, the suggested NKR policy change is used as a hypothetical case study to explore more general questions around the provision of financial benefits to donors, and to illustrate how one may navigate ethical questions that arise when considering such policies. Recall that the potential harms to living kidney donors can include medical and surgical effects of kidney removal; psychological impact of kidney removal as it relates to quality of life and various interactions with others; and the economic impact of kidney removal both direct and indirect relating to current and future employment. The National Kidney Registry (NKR) is a voluntary network of 86 transplant centers in the United States. NKR supports living kidney transplants using novel computer algorithms to facilitate exchanges for patients where an intended donor and recipient are either incompatible (by ABO blood group or HLA sensitization), or poorly HLA matched. The policy takes effect when the donor leaves home to travel to the donation site, and terminates one year after any post-donation complications. It is meant to provide coverage for any losses that may be incurred through donation and not covered by other insurance policies, including travel accidents, disability, or loss of life. Medical complications are defined using the exact Medicare definition, and must be a direct result of the donor surgery. The medical complications expense benefit is $250,000 with a $5,000 deductible. Accidental death and dismemberment is for one year and provides up to $1 million of coverage for accidental deaths and dismemberment. The temporary disability benefit pays $100 per week up to a maximum of $1,500. The permanent disability benefit pays $5,000 per month up to a maximum of $250,000. It is a similar insurance program that is offered by the Living Donor Organ Network through member centers. The insurance costs about $550 per donor, which is paid by the NKR. The idea for provision of such insurance to all living donors has developed from initial work done by the South Eastern Organ Procurement Foundation (SEOPF). The NKR is considering a policy change to include a wider scope for its potential living donors. The suggestion is to extend donor insurance to all living donors who donate through the NKR, rather than just to non-directed donors. Central ethical questions include whether extending insurance to all NKR donors could be considered an unethical valuable exchange or unreasonable inducement to donate, or whether such insurance would constitute unfair inducement for donors to work through the NKR rather than through other transplantation programs. Given these potential concerns, can it be ethically supported to extend donor insurance and prioritization for future transplantation to all NKR living donors? This analysis will tease out the impact of this proposed policy change within the NKR, and suggest an ethical framework for use by other transplant centers or networks that may consider similar policy changes. In transplantation, we are concerned with fairly distributing a scarce resource among many persons in need. We are also concerned with the interests and welfare of donors, the interests of the public, and fair stewardship of this scarce resource. To balance these various interests and to determine rules for distribution, a utilitarian approach to distribution is often utilized. Utilitarianism states that right actions (or policies) are those that lead to the greatest good for the greatest number of people. That is, policies are set to ensure that the scarce resource provides the greatest benefit to the greatest number of affected patients. This forms the basic foundation for grounding various ethical commitments and goals in transplantation. Even if one holds to another ethical approach or theory, this framework can still be recognized as applicable and foundational to transplantation. In Medical Ethics, we are often focused on obligations owed by the clinician to the individual patient. Commonly applied Medical Ethics frameworks reflect this. For example, deontology is an ethical approach that says ethical rules describe duties and obligations clinicians owe to their patients. One such approach is that ethical rules may be derived from the inherent worth and dignity of the patient as a person. The Kantian idea of respect for persons has been very influential in Medical Ethics, and may be used to derive ethical rules and duties owed to the patient because clinicians respect the patient as a person and do not merely regard a patient as an object. Such rules include respecting the patient’s right to direct their own medical care and make their own decisions, refraining from deception or dishonesty, helping patients to the best of one’s ability and skill, and the like. Another well-known ethical framework is the principles framework. It recognizes four principles that describe the ethical commitments of clinicians within the clinician-patient relationship. The clinician should provide benefit, avoid harm, and respect autonomy, while also being concerned with justice. These frameworks generally focus on what is owed to the individual patient. The clinician has obligations to serve the interests of the individual patient as described by these moral rules or principles. There may therefore appear to be a tension between commonly applied frameworks in medical ethics and the utilitarian framework we use in this analysis. We maintain that these are compatible, given the unique relationships and resource limitations that constrain transplant centers. We argue that even the deontologist or principle-based ethicist will on reflection acknowledge the validity of the utilitarian distribution framework that will be used as basis for this analysis. The deontologist and principlist are concerned respectively with rules and principles that govern patient-practitioner relationships and protect the interests of the individual patient. However, when it comes to transplantation of scarce human organs, we are confronted with many patients who are competing for said organs, and living donors whose interests must also be protected. In trying to secure and protect the interests of individual patients when deciding how to distribute this scarce resource, the deontologist and principlist will try to serve the interests of each individual patient fully as required by their Medical Ethics frameworks, but will fall short because of the restricted nature of the resource. What we end up with is a utilitarian type distributive system, which seeks to serve the interests and welfare of all those competing patients and donors to the maximal degree possible. It allows the clinician to fulfill obligations owed to the most patients and to the greatest extent possible. The utilitarian guiding principle used in this report will be that transplant policies should seek to maximize the interests and welfare of the most people, including the kidney recipient, the donor, the program and its professionals, and the public. The transplant center must serve the interests of the most patients and donors possible to the maximal extent possible, given the inherent resource-limitations in transplantation. From this ethical basis, two ethical principles can be stipulated regarding protection of living donors. In contemporary clinical practice these principles are widely accepted in the transplant community, even if they are not explicitly stated, and are part of the guiding principles of transplant programs. In clinical practice this means that the harms associated with donating a kidney should be minimized or mitigated as far as is possible. This idea can be justified in a number of ways: (a) If donors come to harm or suffer financial setbacks because of donating, it decreases the welfare of those donors with negative consequences for affected donors, their families, and the public. (b) Donation related harms and financial setbacks would make people less likely to donate and have a negative impact on the donation process, patients needing transplants, and consequently the broader public. (c) It is in keeping with obligations of harm avoidance or non-maleficence central to medicine, which can be grounded in any of the approaches to bioethics. Donors must accept various risks when agreeing to donate, and harms cannot always be avoided. A central tenet for those obtaining informed consent from donors is to outline reasonable expectations of risk so that donors have the necessary information to support their decision to donate. In clinical practice harm to donors should be avoided or minimized so that donors are no worse off for donating. When it comes to financial matters, this means donation should be a financially neutral event for the donor. The idea of removing disincentives to donation (and particularly financial disincentives) have been advanced by several authors. Authors usually distinguish between compensation and financial incentives as different forms of payment to living donors. There is an ethical and legal distinction between compensation and incentives as defined above. Legal and ethical norms tend to support compensation; financial payments for donation related costs are permitted by American law. Apart from the issue with present legislation, there are generally four arguments offered to show why financial incentives are thought to be ethically problematic. The argument is that if incentives are provided, it may induce people to donate who would not otherwise do so. In a sense, the incentive interferes with the voluntariness and freedom of the decision to donate and holds sway over the person that influences their ability to provide informed consent. In addition, it is often thought that the greater the benefit or payment, the greater the risk of unreasonable influence over the decision to donate. Even if incentives increased short term donation rates, they would not serve the greater interests of all. If the freedom of people to choose are undermined, their interests are compromised. The argument states that not everything should have a financial value, and not everything should be sold in markets. Placing a financial value on things that are intrinsically valuable cheapens them and should not happen. For example, freedom is of incalculable value; it would not be ethical to allow someone to sell their freedom. Related to this argument is the idea that a gift of a transplant organ is a different kind of interaction than selling an organ. The first is a gift, an altruistic act, one where one person helps another because of moral considerations. The second is a commercial transaction, reducing the participants to buyer and seller, or to businessperson and customer, which is argued to be the wrong motivation for donating or receiving an organ. It changes the type of interaction, and necessarily changes the relationship and obligations that exist between the parties. The argument is that providing incentives would change the nature of the interaction from an altruistic action between equals to a business transaction. This would lead to a moral repugnance among some potential donors, who would then decline to donate. These ideas are based on the theoretical work of Richard Titmuss, who compared the altruistic blood donation system in the UK with the financially incentivized blood donation system in the US. Those who are lower on the socio-economic spectrum may perceive an even greater inducement to donate when incentives are introduced. Some have argued that the poor are especially vulnerable to unreasonable influence caused by financial inducements, and that their autonomy with regards to donation is substantially affected by financial incentives. These arguments have remained persuasive to many, and exchanging valuable considerations for organs therefore remains illegal. Some authors have argued that they are mostly theoretical or conceptual arguments, based in normative and ethical argumentation, and have not been extensively empirically tested. It is therefore controversial to what extent incentives can be consistent with the ethical obligations of the transplant program. At the very least, we can state that any incentive that is likely to lead to unreasonable inducement, commodification of the body, decline in donation rates, or exploitation of the vulnerable is ethically problematic. Financial benefits provided to donors should therefore be scrutinized carefully to see whether such benefits are out of bounds. Extending donor insurance to all donors clearly provides a financial benefit to donors. The insurance provides coverage for possible complications and harms directly associated with the act of donation. It is therefore an avenue for managing possible donation associated harms and losses that are not financially provided for in another way. The goals of donor insurance therefore seem onsistent with removing disincentives to donation, and ensuring that donors are as far as possible no worse off for donating. The insurance policy costs $550 per donor, and as such is not an extraordinary amount, nor is it paid directly to the donor. Rather, an insurance benefit is provided that would only cover donation related complications. The potential for unreasonable inducement seems quite small. Insurance is an effort at harm mitigation and reduction of financial loss, rather than providing valuable exchange for the organ. Given these considerations, it does not appear as if there is any risk for creating a business transaction or placing a price tag on a kidney. The risk of exploitation of the vulnerable appears minimal, as those who are poor will not be financially better off after donation. The policy is meant to remedy donation related risks and losses, and not offer financial inducement. It may replace financial losses, but the insurance does not generate new income. In addition, the usual process for donor evaluation will remain, which includes an additional set of safeguards against exploitation. In particular, the Independent Donor Advocate, a required participant in the living donor evaluation and informed consent process at all transplant centers, will be present to monitor possible exploitation. It therefore seems unlikely that donor insurance would lead to exploitation of vulnerable and marginalized patients. One possible concern some may raise is that availability of donor insurance through the NKR may provide incentive for donors to work with NKR rather than other paired exchange networks who do not offer such insurance. This concern does not hold up to scrutiny, since donor insurance is aimed at removing donation disincentives and mitigating donation related losses. If one transplant program offers an injury or loss management program when others do not, it is not unfair or unethical for donors to prefer that program. For example, if one transplant program introduces innovative surgical procedures that have evidence based lower complication rates and/or better outcomes for donors, it is very reasonable that donors would choose that program. On the contrary, one can argue it would be incumbent on other transplant programs to consider implementing similar procedures if they are shown to improve donor outcomes. Similarly, if the NKR implements a program that aims at removing disincentives and mitigating donation related risks, it would be incumbent on other programs to consider such practices. Extending insurance to all donors would incur costs to the program. It could represent a substantial financial investment, given the amount of paired exchanges facilitated by NKR. The increase in cost may well be justified by the ethical goals of removing disincentives and ensuring donors are not worse off for donating. However, it would be important to consider whether there are other means by which these same goals could be reached at less cost. Simply put: is the donor insurance the best use of the program’s resources, or are there other ways in which the program can remove disincentives and compensate donors at a lower expenditure? A notable alternative use for such funds would be reimbursement for lost wages. Such reimbursement would also aim at removing disincentives towards donation and ensuring that donors are no worse off, while potentially increasing donation rates. Is this a better use of the program’s financial resources, or should both benefits be considered? The lost wage coverage is currently being evaluated by the American Society of Transplant Surgeons. Finally, should any of these compensations be offered, the impact and cost-effectiveness of these interventions should be studied. In this way any unforeseen effects can be detected early, and permit appropriate changes in policy. Furthermore, by studying the policy and its effects valuable data can be generated that can provide guidance for other transplant programs who are considering similar compensation policies. Underlying any programmatic financial considerations should be the goals of doing more kidney transplants, removing more patients from dialysis, while leaving donors no worse off for donating, thereby reducing healthcare expenditures. This results in a net gain for society in general.